Section I: T1
We begin with an interpreted toy language L with names (c1, c2...) one-place function symbols [I believe this is supposed to be like "father of", interpreted as a function in (e, e)] (f1, f2...) and one-place predicates (p1, p2...). Initially we "will follow Tarski in supposing that in L the sense of every expression is unambiguously determined by its form." We define:
1) singular terms: names, variables [wait, where are the variables?], and function symbols followed by singular terms [father(x), father(m)]
2) formulas: predicate^singular term, ~^formula, formula^formula, Ax(formula).
3) sentences: closed formulas.
Variables and assignments are introduced. An assignment can be thought of as a sequence s = , where si's are objects, which assigns objects to the variables `x1', `x2'... We will abbreviate ``true on assignment s" as ``true_s". We also employ ``denotes_s", e.g. `x1' denotes_s s1 on assignment s. Annoyingly, we use ``fulfills" for function symbol-pairs and ``applies to" for 1-place predicates.
T1: an inductive characterization of denotes_s and truth_s (using # for quine-corners:)
(A)
1. `xk' denotes_s sk.
2. `ck' denotes_s what it denotes.
3. `fk(e)' denotes_s an object a iff (i) there is an object b that `e' denotes_s and (ii) `fk' is fulfilled by .
(B)
1. #pk(e)# is true_s iff (i) there is an object a that e denotes_s, and (ii) `pk' applies to a.
2. #~e# is true_s iff e is not true_s.
3. #e1 & e2# is true_s iff e1 is true_s and e2 is true_s.
4. #Axk e# is true_s iff for each sequence s* that differs from s at the kth place at most, e is true_s*.
In the case of sentences truth, we have:
(C)
A sentence is true iff it is true_s for some (\every) s.
This is the Truth Characterization (TC) of T1. TC reduces one semantic notion, truth, to three others: (1) denotation for names, (2) predicate denotation (or "application"), (3) function symbol fulfillment. We introduce "primitive denotation" for these three things; T1 explains truth in terms of primitive denotation. We can also explain denotation for arbitrary closed singular terms, like `f1(c1)', in terms of the primitive denotations of its parts. Hence Tarski's T1 is compositional.
To have explained truth in terms of primitive denotation is, Field concedes, an important achievement. It is good for the purposes of model theory:
"...[I]n model theory we are interested in such questions as: given a set Gamma of sentences, is there any way to choose the denotations of the primitives of the language so that every sentence of Gamma will come out true given the usual semantics for the logical connectives? For questions such as this, what we need to know is how the truth-value of a whole sentence depends on the denotations of its primitive nonlogical parts, and that is precisely what T1 tells us. So at least for model-theoretic purposes, [T1] is precisely the kind of explication we need. (351)"
Languages where sense is determined by form.
What should we make of this stipulation of Tarski's? It is not fulfilled by natural languages: I can use the word ``John" to refer to different people on different occasions, and I can use phrases like ``takes grass" to mean different things on different occasions as well. Field writes that it``seems clear that ...there is no remotely palatable way" of extending the theory of truth Tarski actually gave, which is a bit different from T1, to sentences like `John takes grass.'"
If we use T1 as the model, though, "there is no difficulty...The only point about languages containing `John' or `grass' or `I' is that for such languages `true', `denotes', and other semantic terms make no sense as applied to expression types, they make sense only as applied to tokens." It is suggested that we would need to reinterpret e.g. B(2) of T1 as:
(B) 2. A token of #~e# is true_s iff the token of #e# that it contains is not true_s.
[Something dangerous is going on here, related to not having cleanly separated contexts and indices. We shouldn't speak of tokens occurring within tokens, because at some index values there will be no tokens. For example, if the operator were metaphysical necessity, we couldn't really speak of `the token contained in it'.]
Field notes that "this analysis leaves entirely out of account the ways in which `I' and `John' differ: it leaves out of account, for instance, [the character of `I'.] But that is no objection to the analysis, for the analysis purports merely to explain truth in terms of primitive denotation; it does not purport to say anything about primitive denotation, and the differences between `I' and `John'...are purely differences in how they denote." (352).
If we want to re-write T1-(A) [the characterization of denotation_s] so that it is flexible enough to allow for the introduction of new names into the language and so ``does not rely on the actual vocabulary that the language contains at a given time," it is easy to do so:
T1(A)
1. The kth variable denotes_s sk.
2. If e1 is a name, it denotes_s what it denotes.
3. If e1 is a singular term and e2 a function symbol, then #e2(e1)# denotes_s a iff (i) there is an object b that e1 denotes, (ii) e2 is fulfilled by the ordered pair (a, b).
We "can generalize the definition of truth_s in a similar manner. This shows that, in giving a TC, there is no need to utilize the particular vocabulary used at one temporal stage of a language, for we can instead give a more general TC which can be incorporated into a diachronic theory of the language."
Section II: T2.
T2 is more closely modeled on the theory Tarski actually offered: it does not use any semantic concepts (no "primitive denotation") in its definition of truth_s (and hence truth simpliciter.)
``How did Tarksi achieve this result? Very simply: first, he translated every name, predicate, and function symbol of L into English, then he utilized these translations in order to reformulate clauses 2 and 3(ii) of (A) and clause 1 of (B). For simplicity, let's use c1, c2, etc., as abbreviations for the English expressions that are translations of the words `c1', `c2'...of L: e.g.: if L is...German and `c1' is `Deutschland,' then `c1' is an abbreviation for `Germany.'"
Hence the formulation of T2:
T2: an inductive characterization of denotes_s and truth_s (using # for quine-corners:)
(A)
1. `xk' denotes_s sk.
2. `ck' denotes_s ck.
3. `fk(e)' denotes_s an object a iff (i) there is an object b that `e' denotes_s and (ii) a is fk(b).
(B)
1. #pk(e)# is true_s iff (i) there is an object a that e denotes_s, and (ii) pk(a).
2. #~e# is true_s iff e is not true_s.
3. #e1 & e2# is true_s iff e1 is true_s and e2 is true_s.
4. #Axk e# is true_s iff for each sequence s* that differs from s at the kth place at most, e is true_s*.
How do we get the translations right, though, in order to ensure that e.g. `ck' denotes_s ck? We need a requirement of coreferentiality to define an `adequate translation': are an adequate translation iff (i) e1 and e2 are coreferential, (ii) e2 contains no semantic terms [this is to avoid translating e.g. `Deutschland' as `the referent of `Deutschland' in German.'] (355). Of course, Tarski did not reduce the notion of an adequate translation to nonsemantic terms. This is not, by itself, a devastating objection to T2; Tarski was merely relying on the resources of a interpreted metalanguage:
"[This] is no objection to...T2, for the notion of an adequate translation is never built into the truth characterization and is not, properly speaking, part of a theory of truth. On Tarski's view we need to adequately translate the object language into the metalanguage in order to give an adequate theory of truth for the object language; this means that the notion of giving an adequate translation is employed in the methodology of giving truth theories, but it is not employed in the truth theories themselves." (355).
We are left with T1 and T2, both perfectly good on their own terms. It is still true that T1 employs semantic vocabulary while T2 does not. Now we are better suited to address the question of whether this means T2 is more philosophically significant than T1.
Philosophy.
We ask: for what purpose do we want a definition of truth with no semantic terminology? The first desideratum that might come to mind is that we want to explain the meaning of the word 'true.' But that cannot be what we are after here. For example, the kind of definition of truth we will wind up with differs for different languages. Yet that misses something important about truth!
What Tarski hints at in his writings is that he is on a quest to make semantic terminology, like ``true", compatible with physicalism. Field quotes Tarksi writing that without the project he is embarking on, "it would be difficult to bring [semantics--HF] into harmony with the postulates of the unity of science and of physicalism."
Section III. Physicalism and Ontological Reduction.
We could call the view that Tarski seems opposed to---one that holds that there is no reduction of semantic terms to Physicalist ones---``semanticalism." (Compare this to ``Cartesianism", the view that there are irreducibly mental facts.) When we confront the terms of some special science, like "gene" in biology, from the point of view of a reducing science, we have two options: we can either try to account for it, or reject the need to account for it, in the way a physicalist should reject a call to explain ghosts or vital essences.
Now consider the semantic project: someone says "schnee ist weiss" to me, and I wish to classify the utterance as true. Part of the explanation is that snow is white: that is a perfectly physicalistically acceptable fact with a physical explanation. But another part is left unaccounted for: the relationship between the (physicalistically acceptable) whiteness of snow and ``the German utterance being true...It is this connection that seems so difficult to explicate in a way that would satisfy a physicalist, i.e., in a way that does not involve the use of semantic terms."
Section IV. T2 is not superior to T1 for the purposes of ontological reduction.
Tarski also set himself a condition of formal adequacy on theories of truth, which seems, in his writings, not to be straightforwardly connected to considerations of reductionism.
(M) Any condition of the form
(2) Ae [e is true <-> B(e)]
should be accepted as an adequate definition of truth iff it is correct and `B(e)' is a well-formed formula containing no semantic terms.
As noted, T1 is a partial reduction. But T2, which meets this criterion, is, Field argues, still inadequate, because (M) is inadequate. ``Correctness", if this is glossed merely as extensional equivalence, is too weak for ontological reduction.
[Objection: we don't need to conclude that 'true' is a natural kind, only that all instances of it can be physicalistically accounted for: c.f. 'poison.' There may not be any kind of extensional unity in terms of which ontological reduction can be explained.]
Field's case study in "why extensional equivalence is not a sufficient standard of reduction" (362) is the concept of valence in chemistry. We can give a purely extensional definition of valence, which would have been useful to working chemists even in an era before chemistry was reduced to physics:
(3) (Ae) (An) (E has valence n iff: E is potassium and n is +1, or E is sulphur and n is -2, or...etc, etc.)
If we had not reduced chemistry to physics, valence would have had to be occammed, according to the physicalist. In other words, (3) by itself would not save valence from Occam's Razor, despite the fact that it is extensionally adequate and the word `valence' does not appear on the other side of the biconditional in (3).
Field wants the analogy to be taken in a certain way. He does not claim that T2 is as trivial as (3); he does claim, though, that "roughly...T2 minus T1 is as trivial as (3) is" (363).
Note, first, that the notion of valence can be used to give a recursive definition of valence for chemical compounds. This extended notion of valence is, well, compositional: the valence of the compound depends on the valences of its constituents and how they're stuck together. This is like the reduction of truth to primitive denotation. However, in both cases, something basic remains unexplained (primitive denotation/primitive valence), and this is the very thing that must be explained if reduction is to succeed.
We can get at what Field means by "T2 minus T1" by isolating a component of T2 that is like (3), the enumerative definition of valence:
(DE) To say that the name N denotes a given object a is the same as to stipulate that either a is France and N is `France', or a is Germany and N is `Germany,' or...
This is Tarski's account of proper names in English. "It seems clear," Field writes, "that DE and DG (an analogous definition of denotation for German) do not really reduce truth [primitive denotation] to nonsemantic terms, any more than (3) reduces valence to nonchemical terms." (365).
We might ask what a reduction the naming relation (N denotes a) to nonsemantic terms would look like, if there were one. For that, we can reference Russell's theory of properly proper names, which were reduced using the notions of sense-data and acquaintance. Russell's theory is not successful, but it has the form of a theory that, if successful, would be non-circular--it would be a true reduction. To this we can add that a more successful account of naming, Kripke's causal-chain theory, is still in the works: while Kripke's theory doesn't (by Kripke's own lights) give a "purely causal" account of naming, it is possible that some such theory will succeed. [For example, it seems that Kripke gets right certain counterfactuals that Russell gets wrong; and establishing the right kind of counterfactual dependence is one way of getting beyond merely extensional equivalence.]
What value did Tarski attach to clauses like DE, which we have claimed to be the difference between T1 and T2? It is hard to say. We do know that T2 was the basis for some extravagant claims on Tarski's behalf, such as his claim that "the problem of establishing semantics on a scientific basis is completely solved." [qtd. by Field, 369]. In other places Tarski suggested that such a clause could explain the meaning of "denote." But this isn't right, since once again, DE/DG are merely extensional and don't capture the fact that we should give the same meaning for "denote" to different languages, since different languages denote in the same way. "In fact, it seems prety clear that denotation definitions like DE and DG have no philosophical interest whatever" (369).
Section V. Why do we want a notion of Truth?
A notion of truth might serve any number of purposes, but a primary or original purpose is "to aid us in utilizing the utterances of others in drawing conclusions about the world." We need truth, both semantically and pragmatically conceived, to understand "(i) the circumstances under which what another says is likely to be true, and (ii) how to get from a belief in the truth of what he says to a belief about the extralinguistic world" (371). We need accounts of trust and truthfulness, as well as assertability (the connection between the assertability conditions of "p" and those of "`p' is true".)
This seems right to Field, and "it gives more insight than was given in Sections II and IV into why it is that neither T1 nor T2 can reasonably be said to explain the meaning of the term `true'--even when a theory of primitive reference is added to them." The reader is referred to Dummett's article "Truth" and what Dummett therein says about "Frege-style truth definitions".
Field also takes a swipe at a kind of complacentist position that takes its inspiration from the Neurath's boat analogy:
" 'Why [in light of an explication of truth in terms of assertability norms] do we need causal (etc.) theories of reference? The words `true' and `denotes' are made perfectly clear by schemas like (T). To ask for more than these schemas--to ask for causal theories of reference to nail language to reality--is to fail to recognize that we are at sea on Neurath's boat: we have to work within our conceptual scheme, we can't glue it [what?] to reality from the outside.' " (372)
Field responds in italics: "The reason why accounts of truth and primitive reference are needed is not to tack our conceptual scheme onto reality from the outside; the reason, rather, is that without such accounts our conceptual scheme breaks down from the inside." Here, I take Field to be using "our conceptual scheme" to mean "physicalism." [I have no better understanding of "inside" and "outside" metaphors in this context than I usually do.]